Discussion post: Visual dysfunction in children (1-3 paragraphs)
Amanda, a 16-year-old female suffers from a pituitary gland tumor. This tumor presses on the optic chiasm and results in a condition where Amanda’s right eye can no longer see the right side of the visual field. It also affects her left eye such that it can no longer see the left side of the visual field.
Jacob, a 5-year-old, has scarring on the fusiform gyrus secondary to seizures. This damage has resulted in ventral stream disruption and in particular, problems with facial recognition.
What functional deficits might affect Amanda and Jacob? Considering their different developmental levels, list the deficits and describe their potential effects in the physical, cognitive-academic, and social-emotional areas of functioning. What interventions are appropriate, and how would they differ for each of these two individuals?
Articles attached
Object recognition with severe spatial deficits
in Williams syndrome: sparing and breakdown
Barbara Landau a,*, James E. Hoffman
b , Nicole Kurz
b
a Department of Cognitive Science, Krieger Hall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21218, USA
b University of Delaware, Newark, DE, USA
Received 31 March 2002; revised 2 September 2004; accepted 23 June 2005
Abstract
Williams syndrome (WS) is a rare genetic disorder that results in severe visual-spatial cognitive
deficits coupled with relative sparing in language, face recognition, and certain aspects of motion
processing. Here, we look for evidence for sparing or impairment in another cognitive system—
object recognition. Children with WS, normal mental-age (MA) and chronological age-matched
(CA) children, and normal adults viewed pictures of a large range of objects briefly presented under
various conditions of degradation, including canonical and unusual orientations, and clear or blurred
contours. Objects were shown as either full-color views (Experiment 1) or line drawings
(Experiment 2). Across both experiments, WS and MA children performed similarly in all conditions
while CA children performed better than both WS group and MA groups with unusual views. This
advantage, however, was eliminated when images were also blurred. The error types and relative
difficulty of different objects were similar across all participant groups. The results indicate selective
sparing of basic mechanisms of object recognition in WS, together with developmental delay or
arrest in recognition of objects from unusual viewpoints. These findings are consistent with the
growing literature on brain abnormalities in WS which points to selective impairment in the parietal
areas of the brain. As a whole, the results lend further support to the growing literature on the
functional separability of object recognition mechanisms from other spatial functions, and raise
intriguing questions about the link between genetic deficits and cognition.
q 2005 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
Keywords: Ventral Stream; Object Recognition; Williams syndrome
Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510
www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT
0022-2860/$ – see front matter q 2005 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2005.06.005
* Corresponding author. Tel.: C1 410 516 5255.
E-mail address: landau@cogsci.jhu.edu (B. Landau).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510484
In this paper, we report evidence that some mechanisms of object recognition can
develop without impairment even while other aspects of spatial representation are severely
impaired. Our evidence comes from people with Williams syndrome, a genetic disorder
which gives rise to an unusual cognitive profile including severe spatial deficits together
with relatively spared language 1 . The striking imbalance between two major cognitive
systems has suggested to some that genetic defects can have specific cognitive targets
during development (Bellugi, Marks, Bihrle & Sabo, 1988; Jordan, Reiss, Hoffman &
Landau, 2002; see also, Frith, 1992). Such targeting has been attributed to modular
organization of cognition (Bellugi et al., 1988; Clahsen & Almazan, 1998) or
specialization in streams of processing in the mind and brain (e.g. Atkinson, Braddick,
Anker, Curran, Andrew and Wattam-Bell, 2003; Dilks, Landau & Hoffman, 2005). The
present studies provide support for specific targeting in a genetic deficit, as they show that
basic mechanisms of object recognition can be spared even though other aspects of spatial
representation are severely impaired. We show that, while children with Williams
syndrome cannot reproduce the spatial organization of even moderately complex figures
(see Fig. 1), they can recognize a wide range of familiar objects under varying conditions
of degradation.
Testing the possibility that a specific cognitive system is spared in a case of genetic
impairment requires several steps. First, it requires evidence that the cognitive system in
question is specialized, that is, different from other knowledge domains or functions on
computational, neural, and/or psychological grounds. Such evidence is abundant in object
recognition, and we discuss it below. Second, it assumes that genetic deficits can, in
principal, target certain cognitive systems while leaving others either partially or fully
spared. As we discuss below, this assumption is complex and currently under debate.
Ultimately, the debate can only be resolved by empirical study, which we offer here.
Finally, any empirical test requires sufficient fine-grained detail to examine key aspects of
normal cognitive architecture. If patterns of performance are both quantitatively and
qualitatively similar to normal groups, it is reasonable to conclude that basic aspects of the
architecture are spared. Alternatively, detailed patterns of difference can shed light on
which aspects of the architecture are robust and which are vulnerable in genetic deficit.
The experiments we present will test key aspects of the object recognition system in order
to determine how, if at all, performance differs from normal.
1. Object recognition as a specialized system
Thinking of human object recognition as a specialized system is not a new idea. At least
since the work of Marr (1982), it has been acknowledged that one of the central
computational goals of the visual system is to rapidly recognize objects under a wide
range of viewing conditions. The object recognition system is designed to represent
1 We attach no technical meaning to the term ‘severe’, but rather, use it to describe the hallmark pattern of
Williams syndrome, in which children, adolescents, and even adults carry out visual-spatial constructive tasks
such as block construction at the level of four-year-old normal children.
Fig. 1. Sample copies of model figures (row 1) drawn by two children with Williams syndrome (rows 2 and 3) and
one normally developing child matched for mental age (row 4). KBIT scores represent IQ, not raw scores used for
matching.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 485
objects—primarily by their shapes—in a way that renders them recognizable over changes
in irrelevant spatial properties such as size, translation, and viewpoint. Thus, object
recognition is inherently spatial. The specific computational problems involved in visual
object recognition include segmenting the image from background, parsing it into edges
and/or parts, and representing the overall configuration, usually determined by the spatial
relationships among parts. The resulting representation must support matching to an
incoming image over changes in the object’s lighting, size, viewpoint, etc. (Marr, 1982;
Palmeri & Gauthier, 2004).
Arguments and evidence suggest that the computational solutions to these problems are
unique to objects. For example, researchers have suggested that object shape is
represented by the distributed activity of a population of neurons tuned to specific
viewpoints (Logothetis & Sheinberg, 1996; Palmeri & Gauthier, 2004). Recent data from
brain imaging suggests that the computations involved in recognizing objects are carried
out in distributed, but constrained areas of the brain that are distinct from areas that process
face recognition (Palmeri & Gauthier, 2004; Pietrini, Furey, Ricciardi, Gobbini, Wu and
Cohen, 2004). Presumably, this specialized computational system has evolved to allow us
to rapidly and efficiently recognize objects, perhaps even as soon as we know that an
object is there (Grill-Spector & Kanwisher, 2005).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510486
A particularly difficult problem for the visual system is recognition of objects from
partial, sometimes degraded images that result from viewing objects from different
viewpoints, which often occlude and distort important features. Some theories suggest
that the visual system constructs a single unified viewpoint-invariant representation (e.g.
Biederman, 1987; Marr, 1982). However the bulk of empirical evidence indicates that
we recognize objects by using viewpoint-dependent representations and interpolating
new viewpoints (Bulthoff, Edelman & Tarr 1995; Tarr & Pinker, 1990; Logothetis,
Pauls, Bulthoff & Poggio 1994; see Palmeri & Gauthier, 2004). The mechanisms of
computing new viewpoints are not well understood, but the capacity to do so is
acknowledged to be complex, and is assumed to be a hallmark of our object recognition
system.
Considerations of cognitive function and brain localization also support the idea that
visual object recognition is specialized. Abundant evidence shows that the human visual
system is composed of separate streams which carry out different kinds of spatial
processing that serve different functions. For example, beyond the primary visual cortex,
the ventral stream processes information about objects and faces. Neurons in
inferotemporal (IT) cortex of monkeys respond to the same object under a variety of
equivalence conditions (Booth & Rolls, 1998; Logothetis et al., 1994) and to neighboring
views of the same object (Tanaka, 1996). In humans, imaging studies show that
homologous areas of cortex are activated during object recognition, suggesting a specific
neural substrate (Kourtzi, Erb, Grodd & Bulthoff, 2003; Palmeri & Gauthier, 2004).
In contrast to the ventral stream areas and their focus on objects, the dorsal stream is
thought to be responsible for processing different kinds of spatial information, including
some kinds of motion and location. For example, the perception of motion coherence—
which requires computing the global direction of individual motion elements—appears to
be processed in area V5/MT (Newsome & Pare, 1988). Still other spatial properties and
functions appear to be governed by other areas of the dorsal stream, especially those
properties pertinent for action (Bridgeman, Gemmer, Forsman & Huemer, 2000; Colby &
Goldberg, 1999; Livingstone & Hubel, 1988; Milner & Goodale, 1995; Ungerleider &
Mishkin, 1982).
Finally, the psychological representation of objects has been shown to be dissociable
from other kinds of representation that depend on spatial organization, even those within
the ventral stream. For example, Moscovitch, Winocur & Behrmann (1997) reported a
brain-damaged patient with severely impaired object recognition who could nevertheless
recognize faces very well. Duchaine and Nakayama (2005) reported the reverse pattern,
developmental prosopagnosics who could not recognize faces, but could recognize
categories of objects such as tools and cars quite well. Milner and Goodale (1995) reported
a patient who was severely impaired in judging a line’s orientation, but could use her
perception of the line to guide action (e.g. posting a letter through a slot). Importantly,
patients who lose the ability to recognize objects often have damage to the ventral stream,
specifically areas of inferotemporal and occipital cortex. These people often perform
worse under degraded conditions such as varying illumination or novel viewpoints (see
Farah, 2000), suggesting that they have lost the hallmark capacity to recognize object
equivalences over such varying conditions.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 487
As a whole, this evidence strongly suggests that the object recognition is specialized in
its computational mechanisms, neural substrate, and psychological function.
2. Genetic deficits and cognitive specialization
Can a genetic deficit target certain cognitive systems while sparing others? This issue is
controversial. One aspect of the controversy concerns whether or not developmental (i.e.
genetic) cases can be used to make the same kinds of inferences about cognitive structure
as adult cases of brain damage. Arguments in favor of selective sparing have often come
from studies of brain-damaged adults, who represent the case of a mature system that
sustains damage. Evidence from brain-damaged adults who can perceive faces but not
objects suggests some type of specialized organization in which systems have been
differentially targeted by the damage (e.g. Moscovitch et al., 1997). In contrast, genetic
deficits have effects even prior to birth, and this raises the question of whether such a
deficit will reflect the same kinds of division of labor as revealed by cases of damage to the
mature brain. A second controversial issue concerns the relationship between genes and
cognition. Genetic changes to an organism will inevitably result in local changes to the
physiology of the brain. The crucial issue is whether such local changes will inevitably
affect cognitive structure.
Views on these two aspects of the controversy lead to very different sets of predictions
about the likely cognitive outcome of any genetic deficit. In one view, it is possible for a
genetic defect to selectively target particular cognitive systems—either because of distinct
computational requirements of the system, or because the defect selectively impairs
streams of processing in the brain that normally support that system. In this view, the local
effects that genes have on brain physiology interact with constraints on knowledge
domains that overdetermine cognitive outcomes. Thus, cognitive domains could be
expected to have normal structure. This possibility is consistent with the idea that different
cognitive domains are computationally distinct, that they have different neural substrates,
and that the internal constraints of the system guide development (e.g. Frith, 1992;
Gallistel, Brown, Carey, Gelman & Keil, 1991; Spelke & Newport, 1998; Tager-Flusberg,
Plesa-Skwerer & Faja, 2003).
Several recent studies in the domain of faces are consistent with this view. For example,
Tager-Flusberg et al. reported that people with Williams syndrome show the face
inversion effect usually observed in normal individuals, suggesting that the face
processing mechanisms operate under normal constraints. In addition, recent reports of
congenital prosopagnosia suggest it is possible to have a specific deficit in face perception
(Behrmann & Avidan, 2005); additional evidence hints that there may be a genetic basis to
this disorder. In this general view, one would predict that mechanisms of object
recognition could be spared even in the context of severe deficits in other areas of visual-
spatial cognition.
In a different view, genetic deficits are also assumed to have widespread local effects on
the development of the brain, but these effects are thought to propogate up to cognitive
structure, as follows. The genetic deficit is assumed to result in impaired cognitive
mechanisms. Interactions between these impaired mechanisms and particular knowledge
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510488
domains will yield differences in cognitive structure. Moreover, the cognitive structures
that are produced will not necessarily (or even probably) show breakdown along the lines
of a normal, mature architecture (Karmiloff-Smith, 1998). Although one might observe
performance that appears similar to a normal profile, closer inspection will likely show
meaningful differences in the underlying cognitive structures. For example, Karmiloff-
Smith, Thomas, Annaz, Humphreys, Ewing and Brace (2004) argue that face processing in
people with Williams syndrome is not normal, but rather, good performance is
accomplished via atypical mechanisms; specifically, they argue that configural processing
of faces in WS people is impaired. This general position is consistent with the idea that,
despite the distinct computational requirements of different cognitive domains, genetic
deficits will likely result in subtle cognitive impairments, including the recognition of
objects.
These strong positions can guide our thinking, but only empirical data can decide
between them. Perhaps more importantly, empirical data can provide us with the
foundation for developing more nuanced theoretical positions.
3. Williams syndrome and object recognition
The case of object recognition in Williams syndrome provides an empirical forum for
doing both of these. Williams syndrome (WS) is a rare genetic disorder (1:20,000 live
births) which is caused by a hemizygous submicroscopic deletion on chromosome
7q11.23. Diagnosis is made on the basis of a unique phenotypic pattern that includes a
characteristic facial profile, disorders of the heart, and anomalies of the viscera. It can also
be verified by a screening technique (fluoride in situ hybridization, FISH) that isolates the
key region of gene deletion (Ewart, Morris, Atkinson, Jin, Sternes and Spallone, 1993;
Frangiskakis, Ewart, Morris, Mervis, Bertrand and Robinson, 1996; Morris, Ewart,
Sternes, Spallone, Stock and Leppert, 1994).
Of most importance to us, however, is the distinctive cognitive profile of individuals with
Williams syndrome, who show severely impaired spatial cognition together with relatively
spared language (Bellugi et al., 1988; Mervis, Morris, Bertrand & Robinson, 1999).
Although WS individuals are also moderately mentally retarded (Mean Composite IQZ55– 60, Mervis, et al., 1999), their unique pattern of spatial deficit and linguistic strength sets
them apart from other groups with comparable retardation, such as Down syndrome (Mervis
et al., 1999). The striking cognitive profile has also motivated some of the strongest
hypotheses of developmental modularity in the field (Bellugi et al., 1988; Pinker, 1994).
Selective sparing in cognitive systems can also be tested by examining differential
breakdown within the broad domain of spatial representation. Growing evidence shows
that spatial representation is not one monolithic system, but rather, is composed of
different sub-systems that are specialized in their computational goals, their functional
properties, and their neural substrates. One example is the contrast between perception of
space and representation of space for action, as described previously. Other functionally
distinct systems include the representation of space for navigation (Aguirre, Zarahn &
D’Esposito, 1998; Gallistel, 1990; Hermer & Spelke, 1996; Newcombe & Huttenlocher,
2000), the multiple representations of space that encode location in different reference
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 489
systems (Andersen, Snyder, Bradley & Xing 1997; Colby & Goldberg, 1999), and the
representation of different kinds of motion such as motion coherence, biological motion,
and form from motion (Schenk & Zihl, 1997; Vaina, LeMay, Bienfrang, Choi &
Nakayama, 1990).
Although the nature of spatial impairment in WS is not well understood at present, there
are indications that it has ‘peaks and valleys’ (cf. Bellugi et al., 1988), raising the
possibility of selective targeting. The most widely observed hallmark of the spatial deficit
appears in so-called ‘visual-spatial construction’ tasks, in which people are asked to
replicate an overall pattern by drawing or assembling parts. Individuals with WS perform
extremely poorly in such tasks, with adolescents performing in the 1st percentile—roughly
at the level of a normal four-year-old (Bellugi et al., 1988; Mervis et al., 1999; see Fig. 1
for some examples). In these tasks, the deficient performance of WS children can be traced
to faulty spatial representations of the individual blocks and their relations rather than
faulty executive processes (Hoffman, Landau & Pagani, 2003). In particular, children with
WS have trouble discriminating the ‘handedness’ of the individual blocks which are often
split in half by color, and have distractors that are mirror-images. Additionally, WS
children make errors in the spatial arrangement of blocks, often erring on left-right
locations within the model. This raises the possibility that object representation more
generally—and not just mirror-image structures—might be impaired.
On the other hand, growing evidence suggests differential breakdown across other
domains that involve spatial organization of elements. For example, the perception of
biological motion and motion coherence is spared in WS children (Jordan et al., 2002;
Reiss, Hoffman & Landau, 2005), even though perception of form from motion is impaired
(Atkinson, King, Braddick, Nokes, Anker & Braddick 1997; Reiss et al., 2005). Aspects of
visual-manual action appear to be impaired, even relative to mental age matched children
(Atkinson, King, Braddick, Nokes, Anker and Braddick, 1997; Dilks, Landau & Hoffman,
2005). Some mechanisms of global spatial perception are unimpaired (Pani, Mervis &
Robinson, 1999) and there is evidence that face perception is spared, even relative to
chronological age matches (Tager-Flusberg et al., 2003). As a whole, these findings are
consistent with the idea that a genetic defect can result in targeted—rather than omnibus—
spatial breakdown.
4. The current experiments
The case of object recognition affords a further test of this possibility. First, it is a
natural domain that presents a unique computational problem: Using patterns of light
striking the retina, the brain must construct a representation that will enable the perceiver
to later recognize the same object, despite changes in viewpoint and lighting that occur in
natural viewing conditions. This is a task that is easily solved by human observers—even
infants—but cannot yet be solved by machines. Second, evidence from cases of brain
damage in adults already suggests specialization of function: People may lose the ability to
perceive objects, while still being able to act on them or reason about them. Third, the
object recognition system seems to be vulnerable to a variety of effects of degradation
under brain damage. For example, poor lighting or line drawings produces special
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510490
difficulties for agnosics (Farah, 2000), and highly unusual viewpoints produce difficulties
in patients with damage to the right parietal lobe (Warrington & Taylor, 1973). This well-
documented pattern of vulnerability within the object recognition system suggests a way
to examine in detail the degree to which object recognition is spared or impaired.
Recognition of objects under degraded conditions, such as poor lighting, unusual
viewpoint, or line drawings would provide a strong test of sparing, but it is also possible
that some conditions might prove substantially more difficult than others, providing
evidence for both sparing and breakdown.
Therefore, in our first experiment, we examined the capacity of children with WS to
identify objects under degraded conditions. We used two critical manipulations:
Presentation of clear vs. blurred images, and presentation of objects from canonical vs.
unusual viewpoints. These two methods of image degradation can be used to drive down
performance of all groups—including normal children and adults—thereby allowing us to
examine whether patterns of failure are similar or different between WS and normal
individuals. But the manipulations are also of more particular interest with respect to
Williams syndrome.
First, blurring the image is of interest because initial characterizations of the spatial
deficit in WS suggested that they are ‘local processors’ (Bihrle, Bellugi, Delis & Marks,
1989; Deruelle, Mancini, Livel, Casse-Perot & de Schoon, 1999), i.e. they correctly
perceive the features of an object but are deficient in grasping the global configuration of
those features. More recent work (Farran, Jarrold & Gathercole, 2003; Pani, Mervis &
Robinson, 1999), however, indicates that people with WS do correctly perceive
configurations and actually have trouble focusing attention on parts that are members of
larger configurations (Hoffman, Landau, and Pagani, 2003). Blurring an image would
primarily affect the visibility of constituent parts (Hughes, Nozawa, and Kitterle, 1996;
Morrison and Schyns, 2001) while leaving the global shape relatively unaffected.
Therefore, to the extent that people with WS utilize global shape to recognize objects, they
might be less affected by blur than control children who may use both local and global
information for identification.
The second, and more crucial manipulation is canonical vs. highly unusual viewpoints.
Recognizing objects from highly unusual viewpoints might present a special problem for
people with Williams syndrome. Perrett, Oram & Ashbridge (1998) suggest that viewpoint
effects on recognition can be understood in terms of a multiple view theory of object
recognition in which the current view is matched to multiple views that are stored in
inferotemporal cortex that have been laid down by previous experiences with that object.
Novel views do not have a matching representation and must be recognized by partial
activation of nearest neighbor views, which will be slower than matches for canonical
views.
This theory, however, does not directly account for findings with highly unusual views.
Unusual views are taken from a perspective that foreshortens the principal axis of the
object and often occludes many of its salient features (Humphreys & Riddoch, 1984). This
precludes the kind of automatic object recognition that seems to occur with more
canonical views and instead, appears to involve a ‘problem solving or executive
component’ (Farah, 2000) in which the observer searches the image for parts that may
provide cues to its identity (Perrett et al., 1998). Given the role of the parietal lobe in
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 491
directing spatial attention (Belmonte & Yurgelun-Todd, 2003), it is perhaps not surprising
that patients with damage to parietal areas are selectively impaired in recognizing these
views (Warrington & Taylor, 1973). The claim that recognition of unusual views requires
executive control is also consistent with the finding that in dual-task experiments, a task
requiring ‘central executive resources’ (random number generation) produced more
interference with unusual views than canonical views (Baragwanath & Turnbull, 2002).
Finally, recognition of unusual views has been found to activate both prefrontal (Kosslyn,
Alpert, Thompson, Chabris, Rauch and Anderson, 1994) and parietal areas (Sugio, Inui,
Matsuo, Matsuzawa, Glover and Nakai, 1999) in fMRI scans, suggesting top-down control
of parietal areas involved with spatial attention.
The role of the parietal lobe in recognition of unusual views suggests that WS subjects
may find such views particularly challenging. Damage to the same parietal areas activated
in recognition of unusual views often results in impairments in tasks such as drawing and
block construction (Benton, 1967; Turnbull, Denis, Mellet, Ghaem & Carey, 2001)—just
those tasks that WS people typically fail. In addition, recent neuroimaging of people with
WS during performance of these spatial tasks shows a reduced activation of these parietal
areas (Meyer-Lindenberg et al., 2004), and other analyses show than WS people have
smaller than normal volume in superior parietal areas (Eckert, Hu, Eliez, Bellugi,
Galaburda and Korenberg, 2005). These observations are consistent with the suggestion by
Atkinson et al. (2003) that WS (and possibly other syndromes) is primarily a dorsal stream
deficit. People with WS might therefore be expected to have a selective deficit in
identifying objects from highly unusual viewpoints, even if their identification from
canonical viewpoints is not deficient.
5. Experiment 1
5.1. Participants
Twelve children with Williams syndrome (mean age 11;0, range 7;4 to 15;3 years), 12
normally developing children who were mental-age matches for the WS group (Mean Age
5;8, Range 4;1 to 7;1 years), 12 normally developing children who were chronological
age-matches for the WS group (Mean Age 11;11, Range 10;6 to 14;3 years) and 12
undergraduates participated. Children with WS were identified through the National WS
Association, and had been positively diagnosed by a geneticist; all but one had also been
diagnosed by the FISH test (the remaining person did not undergo the test). Normal
children in the MA group were matched individually to children with WS, using the
Kaufman Brief Intelligence Test (Kaufman & Kaufman, 1990), which yields a verbal and
non-verbal (Matrices) score. The latter does not have many spatial items, and hence does
not unfairly penalize WS children for their spatial impairment. The mean scores for the
WS children were VerbalZ31.7 (SEZ2.32), MatricesZ18.58 (SEZ1.11); corresponding scores for the MA-matched controls were 29.33 (SEZ2.33) and 18.25 (SEZ1.52). Scores for the CA group were VerbalZ59.6 (SEZ1.46) and MatricesZ38 (SEZ0.99). The mean IQ scores for the three groups were 71.42 (SEZ4.35) for the WS children, 116.2 (SEZ 4.11) for the MA group, and 123 (SEZ2.50) for the CA controls.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510492
In addition, the WS children and ten of the MA controls were tested on the Pattern
Construction Sub-test of the Differential Abilities Scales (Elliot, 1990), which requires
children to replicate a design using individual component blocks, and is the hallmark test
used to diagnose the WS spatial impairment. The scores for the WS children were MZ 81.83, percentileZ1.83, SEZ5.82; scores for the MA controls were, MZ109.2, percentileZ58.1, SEZ6.96. The WS scores are in the range reported by other investigators (see Mervis et al., 1999). All but two WS children fell into the 1st percentile
of performance, thus conforming to the reported pattern of severe spatial deficit. Note that,
although the WS children were matched to normally developing children on verbal and
non-verbal scores (the KBIT), they performed much worse than their MA matches on the
Pattern Construction task, as would be expected. All participants signed informed consent
forms.
5.2. Design, stimuli, and procedures
Participants were asked to name each of a set of 80 full color pictures of objects which
were presented on a computer screen for 500 ms. The objects were drawn randomly from a
set of 320 images consisting of 80 objects (listed in Table 1) in each of four conditions:
(a) canonical view, clear image, (b) canonical view, blurred image, (c) unusual view, clear
image, and (d) unusual view, blurred image. Canonical views were deemed those that
exposed all of each object’s relevant parts; many were full-face views of the object.
Unusual views varied in their orientation, and included foreshortening along the primary
axis, and selection of views from above or below the object. Blurred images were created
by editing the clear images using the Gaussian Blur tool (radius 10) in Photoshop. Objects
were drawn from two sources: The ‘Object DataBank’ available from Michael Tarr (http://
www.cog.brown.edu/wtarr/stimuli.html) and the model set which accompanied Ray Dream Studio 5.5. Examples of objects in each of the four conditions are shown in Fig. 2
and the complete set of images can be viewed at http://hoffman.psych.udel.edu/
ObjectPicturesForWeb.pps.
Each participant saw 80 different objects with an equal number of objects presented in
each of the four conditions. All objects were randomly ordered over eight lists, and
individual WS subjects were assigned the same list as their controls (both MA and CA).
Across lists, each object was represented equally often in each of the four presentation
modes. Responses were recorded verbatim. If the participant was uncertain, the
experimenter encouraged him or her to ‘give your best guess’.
Responses were coded by a person who was blind to participant group. Each response
was presented individually on a computer screen along with the target name (i.e. the name
that was used in creating the objects; see Table 1) and the image of the object that the
participant had viewed when producing the name. The rater used seven categories,
including correct name, correct definition or use, related member of same basic category,
correct superordinate category, similar shape, incorrect name, or do not know. For
example, if a picture of a sunflower was shown, responses would be coded as follows:
‘sunflower’ (correct name), ‘goes in a vase’ (correct use), ‘daisy’ (related member of same
category), ‘plant’ (correct superordinate), ‘clock’ (similar shape), ‘truck’ (incorrect name),
Table 1
List of objects used in Experiments 1 and 2
Anchor Jet plane
Banana Key
Barn Kite
Basket Motorcycle
Baseball bat Mug
Bed Pad lock
Bee Pen
Belt Piano
Bike Pitcher
Binoculars Plant
Blender Pliers
Bottle Pot
Bow (archery) Pretzel
Bridge Pumpkin
Brush Refrigerator
Bulb (light bulb) Ring
Cannon Rollerblades
Carrot Ruler
Cassette tape Scissors
Castle Screwdriver
Chain Shovel
Chair Sink
Clock Sports car
Couch Stool
Crayon Stove
Cup Sunflower
Desk Table
Dresser Tank
Drums Tennis racket
Egg (fried) Toothpaste tube
Eye glasses Trash can
Electric fan Truck
Fork Trumpet
Frying pan Turkey
Glass Umbrella
Grill Violin
Guitar Wagon
Hamburger anger Watch
Hair dryer Windmill
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 493
or ‘do not know’. A second rater coded 20% of the responses, and reliability was 90%.
Where there was disagreement, the first rater’s data were used.
5.3. Results and discussion
An initial analysis examined the accuracy of participants’ labels. Responses in the first
four categories were considered to be correct. Any other response was scored as incorrect.
Naming accuracy (percent correct) as a function of image condition and group is shown in
Fig. 2. Examples of objects used in each condition of Experiment 1
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510494
Fig. 3 (shown as a line graph to emphasize patterns of interaction and additivity between
groups and viewpoint). Fig. 3a shows data for the clear image condition and Fig. 3b shows
data for the blurred image condition.
First, it is apparent that we were effective in our manipulation of the difficulty of
identifying the objects. For both clear and blurred images, participants were more accurate
in naming objects shown in a canonical than in an unusual orientation. Clear images were
identified more accurately than blurred ones. These effects of image quality were
confirmed by significant main effects of Orientation, F(1,44)Z344.7, P!0.001 and Clarity, F(1,44)Z384.5, P!0.001. In addition, there was an Orientation by Clarity interaction, F(1,44)Z84.7, P!0.001 indicating that the effects of combining the two distortions was greater than the additive combination of each distortion in isolation.
Fig. 3. (a) Experiment 1: Clear Images. Mean percent correct (S.E.) over condition and group (Ad: Adults; CA:
chronological age matches; WS: Williams syndrome; MA:mental age matches). (b) Experiment 1: Blurred
Images. Mean percent correct (S.E.) over condition and group (Ad: Adults; CA: chronological age matches; WS:
Williams syndrome; MA: mental age matches).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 495
Across these data, the main effect of Group was significant, F(3,44)Z8.8, P!001, but this was due to the adults’ superior performance. Tukey post-hoc tests showed no
significant differences among the three children’s groups (WS vs. MA, PZ0.72, WS vs. CA, PZ0.62, and MA vs. CA, PZ0.12). The adult group, however was more accurate
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510496
than both the WS group (P!0.002) and MA controls (P!0.001), and marginally better than the CA controls (P!0.056). In addition, there was a Clarity X Group interaction (F(3, 44)Z5.66, P!0.002. To isolate this interaction, we analyzed the difference between clear and blurred images as a function of group. Tukey tests revealed that the WS group showed
smaller effects of blur than either the MA or CA controls (P!0.01 and 0.03, respectively) and were indistinguishable from adults (PO0.98).
The data in Fig. 3 also suggest that the effects of viewpoint and image clarity depended
on group. In order to evaluate the effects of viewpoint, we analyzed the data separately for
clear and blurred images. For clear images (Fig. 3a), there is a striking similarity between
the CA and adult groups as well as between the MA and WS groups. The adults and CA
controls were more accurate across the two viewpoints (MsZ0.96, 0.93) than the other two groups (MsZ0.86, 0.83) and also showed a smaller effect of viewpoint. An analysis of variance on these data revealed a main effect of Group (F(3, 44)Z6.61. Tukey tests on the Group effect revealed that the WS group was less accurate than both the CA and adult
groups (P!0.05 and 0.001, respectively) but did not differ from MA children (PZ0.87). The MA group only differed from the adults (P!0.01).
There was also a significant Group X Viewpoint interaction (F(3,44)Z5.62, P!0.002) . Planned comparisons of the three children’s groups showed that the effect of orientation
was larger for WS compared to CA, t(22)Z2.38, P!0.02 and MA compared to CA, t(22)Z2.37, P!0.02; The WS and MA groups did not differ, t(22)Z0.18, PO0.85. It is possible that the smaller effect of view in the CA group is due to their performance being at
ceiling in the Canonical condition. However, this seems unlikely because performance of
all three groups is quite good in this condition, with all means above 90% (MsZ0.99, 0.96, 0.94, 0.92 for adults, CA, MA, and WS groups). A separate ANOVA on these data
revealed no significant difference among groups, F(2,33)Z1.41, PO0.25. Blurring the image produced a different pattern of results (Fig. 3b). The WS subjects
show a relative improvement in their standing compared to the other groups, and this
appears to be mainly attributed to the larger impact of blur on the CA controls. In fact,
the WS group is now indistinguishable from the CA group. In addition, blurring resulted
in similar effects of orientation for all groups. There were main effects of Group
(F(3,44)Z9.07, P!0.001 and Orientation (F(1,44)Z280.41, P!0.001 but no interaction (F!1). Tukey post hoc tests showed that the main effect of group was due to the adults performing more accurately than all three groups of children (P’s!0.05) which were not different from each other. (WS vs. MA, PZ0.12, WS vs. CA, PZ0.99, and MA vs. CA, PZ0.20).
These results show two main patterns. First, the WS children have very high
performance for canonical views and clear images and their performance drops for
unusual views. Their pattern of accuracy across all conditions is remarkably similar to MA
controls and the performance of both of these groups is worse than that of normal adults.
The CA group appears to occupy an intermediate position. For canonical views of clear
images, they are no different from WS children; for unusual views, they show less impact
of viewpoint, with performance better than both WS children and MA controls.
Second, once images were blurred, the WS children perform as well as the CA children.
In fact, all three groups of children showed comparable accuracy and all groups, including
adults, showed the same relative decline in performance with unusual views.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 497
Why the different effects of blur? Showing clear objects from unusual viewpoints
impaired performance in all of our groups, and in this case, the CA and adult controls were
less affected by unusual views than the WS and MA groups. This advantage disappeared
when images were blurred, however, suggesting that a key ingredient in deciphering
unusual views may be related to analysis of internal features which is weakened by
blurring. This result is consistent with results reported by Lawson & Humphreys (1999)
who studied the effects of foreshortening of the main axis of an object presented as either a
line drawing or a silhouette. Both line drawings and silhouettes preserve the ‘occluding
contour’ of the object and therefore allow the observer to extract the object’s main axis of
elongation. Silhouettes, however, eliminate the possibility of using internal details and
features for identification. Their results showed that extreme foreshortening, similar to the
unusual views in Experiment 1, reduced identification accuracy for both kinds of objects
but particularly for the silhouettes, suggesting that internal features become particularly
important clues to object identity when axis information is no longer available.
The greater effect of unusual views on MA and WS subjects compared to CA controls
in the clear condition suggests that the latter group is better at utilizing the internal details
of objects to identify them from unusual viewpoints. We might expect then that if these
features were more difficult to perceive—as in the blur condition—the CA’s advantage
would disappear and that is what we observed. When objects were blurred, all three groups
of children were comparable. Interestingly, of the three groups of children, the WS group
was the least affected by image blur suggesting that they may rely on the occluding
contour of the object more than control children, even for clear images. This is consistent
with other evidence suggesting that people with WS may have trouble focusing attention
on subparts of a larger pattern. For example, Hoffman et al. (2003) reported that in a
variation of the block construction task, WS children were unable to ignore nearby blocks
when they were cued to attend to a single block in the model.
The foregoing evidence relies on measures of accuracy, and thus might miss some fine-
grained qualitative differences in the way that WS children label objects. Accordingly, we
analyzed the distribution of responses across the seven response categories for the four
groups (see Fig. 4). The number of responses in each response category for each subject
was entered into a c 2 test (SPSS Crosstabs). The only significant interaction of Group with
a Response Category was for Correct Definition or Use (X 2 (15)Z28.9, P!0.02),
reflecting a slightly greater tendency for MA controls to label pictures in terms of their
definition or use. Otherwise, the distribution of responses across the various categories was
similar for all four groups (c 2 s p values ranged from 0.11 for the ‘Do not Know’ category
to 0.68 for the ‘Same Category’ response).
A final set of analyses examined whether the four groups differed in which objects they
found difficult to identify. We computed the average accuracy for each of the 80 objects,
collapsed across the 4 image quality conditions, for each group. We then computed the
correlation between all pairs of groups for accuracy on the 80 objects. The correlations
were significantly greater than zero (P!0.001 for all 6 correlations) and ranged from 0.67 (WS vs. adult groups) to 0.76 (WS vs. MA groups). None of the pairs of correlations
showed reliable differences (all PsO0.17), suggesting that there was a high degree of similarity among all four groups in terms of which objects were easy or difficult to
identify. We also asked whether object identification accuracy depended on object
Fig. 4. Experiment 1: Distribution of response types (M percent, S.E.) over group (Ad: Adults; CA: chronological
age matches; WS: Williams syndrome; MA:mental age matches).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510498
complexity. Two independent raters rank ordered the entire set of 80 objects in terms of
their complexity (correlation between ratersZ0.83). These complexity ratings were not reliably correlated with average accuracy of each object for any of the groups
(correlationsZ0.09, 0.10, 0.21, 0.17 for the WS, MA, CA, and adults, respectively, alphaZ0.05, two-tailed test). Both of these analyses suggest similarity across groups in the relative difficulty of individual objects.
As a whole, the results suggest that object recognition is surprisingly good in children
with WS, certainly much better than might be expected on the basis of their performance in
other areas of spatial cognition such as block construction. Indeed, on the basis of their
standardized verbal scores, they were exactly where one would predict they should be—
comparable to MA controls in every condition. From this perspective, it is surprising that
they were no different from CA controls in identifying objects presented as clear canonical
images, or those presented as blurred images in either canonical or unusual viewpoints.
The WS performance is particularly striking, in light of the fact that recognizing objects
under these circumstances requires that they match an image that they likely never
encountered with a stored representation of the object. This matching likely involves
comparing overlap between two shapes, even though the unusual orientations obscure
aspects of the objects’ shapes.
It would be tempting to conclude that WS children are capable of representing and
extracting an object’s part structure from partial information. However, because the
stimuli were full color renditions of objects, it is always possible that object recognition in
WS depends more on surface features (such as color and texture) than the object’s spatial
structure (e.g. Tanaka & Presnell, 1999; Tanaka, Weiskopf & Williams, 2001). Moreover,
the fact that recognizing objects in unusual orientations can sometimes activate more
parietal areas (Sugio et al., 1999) raises the question of whether a more difficult version of
the task might reveal additional differences between WS children and the normal groups.
In order to test this possibility, we carried out a second experiment, using line drawings of
objects. In these cases, objects can only be recognized by their shapes, not by surface
information such as color or texture.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 499
6. Experiment 2
6.1. Participants
Children were the same as those who participated in Experiment 1, with the exception
of one MA control child, who replaced a child who could no longer participate in our
studies. The new mental age-matched group was still well matched by KBIT verbal (WS
MeanZ33, S.E.Z2.08, control MeanZ33, S.E.Z2.26) and Matrices scores (WS MeanZ 18, S.E.Z1.06, control MeanZ19, S.E.Z1.30). The DAS scores of the WS children had a Mean in the 1st percentile, while the MA matched controls’ Mean was in the 55th
percentile. All participants were tested after Experiment 1.
6.2. Design, stimuli, and procedures
These were identical to Experiment 1, except that the objects were converted to black and
white line drawings (see Fig. 5). Only the clear versions were shown, resulting in a total of
Fig. 5. Examples of objects used in both conditions of Experiment 2.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510500
160 stimuli (80 objects X 2 views). Each subject saw all 80 objects with the view (canonical
or unusual) chosen randomly under the constraint that there was an equal number of
canonical and unusual views. Eight lists of objects in a random order were created and
subjects were randomly assigned a list, matching WS children and their controls on the same
list. Across the lists, each object was shown equally often from the two viewpoints.
6.3. Results and discussion
As in Experiment 1, responses were scored as correct if they were in any of the first four
response categories (correct name, correct definition or use, related category member, or
correct superordinate category); all other responses were scored as incorrect. Fig. 6 shows
the percent correct for the four groups as a function of orientation (canonical or unusual).
Consistent with what we observed in Experiment 1 using full color solid object images,
identification was severely reduced when objects were shown in a unusual orientation,
F(1,44)Z524.7, P!0.001. In addition, there was a main effect of Group, F(3,44)Z20.9, P!0.001) as well as an Orientation X Group interaction, F(3,44)Z7.3, P!0.001 that reflects a similar pattern to the one we observed in Experiment 1 for the clear image
condition. Post-hoc Tukey tests revealed two homogeneous subsets of the Group variable.
WS and MA matches formed one set while the other set consisted of CA matches and
Adults. Members of one subset differed significantly from each member of the other set,
(P!0.001) but not from each other. (WS vs. MA, PZ0.81; CA vs. AD, PZ0.78). Separate analyses were also carried out for the canonical and unusual view conditions,
with a similar result. For both conditions, the WS and MA matches formed one subgroup
and the CA and AD subjects formed another. For canonical views, all groups were above
Fig. 6. Experiment 2: M percent correct (S.E.) over condition and group. (Ad: Adults; CA: chronological age
matches; WS: Williams syndrome; MA:mental age matches).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 501
90% accuracy (MsZ0.92, 0.92, 0.98, 0.97 for WS, MA, CA and adults respective). The WS and MA groups did not differ (PZ0.97) nor did CA and AD groups (PZ0.92). Members of each of the subgroups, however, differed from members of the other group (all
P’s!0.003). For unusual views, WS and MA children were comparable, (MsZ0.54, 0.58, respectively, PZ0.65) as were the CA and adult groups (MsZ0.71, 0.75, respectively, PZ0.65). Members of each of the subgroups differed from members of the other groups (all P’s!0.001).
The Orientation X Group interaction was further analyzed using the difference between
canonical and unusual views for each group. Post-hoc Tukey tests revealed that the WS
group differed from the CA (P!0.02) and AD (P!0.001) groups but not from MA controls (PZ0.59) and the MA group only differed from the Adults (P!0.03). One might worry that the larger effect of orientation on WS subjects compared to CA controls is due
to the CA controls being close to ceiling in the canonical view condition. However, the
WS group was above 90% accuracy in this condition, as in the canonical clear condition of
Experiment 1. Although the interaction should be viewed with caution, the findings here of
the larger orientation effect among WS children than CA controls replicates the findings of
Experiment 1. This suggests there is a real relative weakness for unusual orientations
among WS children relative to CA, but not MA matched children.
These results show that when subjects must rely purely on ‘shape’ information to label
objects, WS children are remarkably good at identifying objects—over 90% with
canonical viewpoints. They are remarkably similar to the MA controls in identification
accuracy, and this holds even when objects are shown in unusual views that produce
substantial deficits in the performance of normal adults. These results are similar to the
clear image condition of Experiment 1 which showed that CA subjects were more accurate
than WS subjects and less affected by unusual views.
Once again, we analyzed the distribution of different error types to determine whether
the four groups differed in the kinds of errors they made. These data are shown in Fig. 7
Fig. 7. Experiment 2: Distribution of responses types (M percent, S.E.) over group (Ad: Adults; CA:
chronological age matches; WS: Williams syndrome; MA:mental age matches).
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510502
and suggest that all four groups have roughly similar profiles across the different response
categories. The number of responses in each response category for each subject was
entered into a c 2 test (SPSS Crosstabs) which resulted in significant interactions between
Group and the following categories: Correct name (Pearson X 2 (81)Z105.6, P!0.05),
Correct Definition or Use (X 2 (15)Z31.3, P!0.01), Related Category member (X2 (27)Z
55.9, P!0.01). The interaction with the ‘Do not Know’ category was marginally significant (X
2 (48)Z64.2, P!0.06). This pattern of significance reflects the higher use of
correct names for objects in the CA and Adult groups compared to WS and MA children
and may partly reflect more sophisticated vocabularies (as shown by their KBIT scores) or
relatively less difficulty in retrieving the correct names. When this analysis was restricted
to just the WS and MA groups, none of the interactions approached significance (all P’sO 0.14), suggesting that these two groups has a similar profile of responses across the various
categories.
A final analysis examined whether groups differed in terms of which objects they found
difficult to identify. Here we were only able to compare the WS and MA groups because
accuracy for many individual objects was at 100% for the CA and AD groups. We
computed the average accuracy for each of the 80 objects, collapsed across the 2
orientation conditions. The correlation between the WS and MA groups across the 80
objects was 0.74, which is significantly different from 0, (t(78)Z9.76, P!0.001), suggesting that WS children and their MA controls were similar, not only in their overall
accuracy of identification but also in terms of which objects they found easy or difficult to
identify. We also examined whether accuracy depended on the rated complexity of the
objects for these two groups. For WS children, the correlation was 0.13 and for the MA
group, it was 0.14, neither of which was significant (WS: t(78)Z1.16, PO0.05 and MA: t(78)Z1.25, PO0.05).
It is important to note that the WS and MA groups, who were relatively less accurate
than the CA and adult groups, were nonetheless quite accurate in this task in an absolute
sense. On average, they correctly recognized approximately 74% of the line drawings
compared to 85% for the CA and AD groups. Even in the most difficult condition, in which
objects were shown in unusual orientations, WS and MA children correctly recognized 54
and 58% of the line drawings, respectively. This is quite high, given that the random
probability of guessing the correct object name is far lower than 1 in 40, which would be
chance in the extremely unlikely event that the subject knew the database for the objects.
Some have conjectured that identifying objects under highly unusual viewpoints may
require a form of cognitive problem-solving, as the visual system may not be designed to
automatically compute these extreme situations (Farah, 2000). Under the circumstances of
severe degradation (line drawing and unusual orientation), this requirement may have
been accentuated. If so, the difference between groups is understandable.
Comparison with the results of Experiment 1 shows that removing color and texture
cues impaired subjects’ performance, with the largest decrement seen when objects were
presented in an unusual view. This is consistent with the notion that multiple mechanisms
may be at work in recognition of unusual views and that other cues to object identity, such
as color or texture, become particularly important when shape information becomes
sufficiently degraded (Farah, 2000). In order to see whether the decrement from unusual
views was larger for line drawings than for full-color objects, an additional analysis of
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 503
variance was conducted comparing the corresponding conditions across the two
experiments (i.e. the data from Experiment 2 vs. those from the clear image condition
of Experiment 1). In this analysis, the Group X Experiment X View interaction was not
significant (F(3,44)!1), suggesting that the performance decrement associated with unusual views for each group was similar for solid full color objects and line drawings.
7. General discussion and conclusions
The present experiments used full color pictures and line drawings of common objects
to examine object identification in children with WS compared to normally developing
children of the same mental (MA) and chronological age (CA). The difficulty of object
identification was manipulated by blurring objects (full color objects) and portraying them
in unusual orientations (color objects and line drawings). Overall, WS and MA children
were remarkably similar under all conditions, both in terms of accuracy and in various
fine-grained details of performance such as which objects they found easy or difficult to
identify. Moreover, the WS children were close to CA matches in their identification of
objects presented in canonical orientations, with differences of 4% to 6% (Experiments 1,
2, respectively). This strong performance by WS children in object recognition stands in
marked contrast to their deficits in certain other spatial tasks. For example, in block
construction (Hoffman et al., 2003), multiple object tracking (O’Hearn, Landau &
Hoffman, 2005), and visual-manual action tasks (Dilks, Landau & Hoffman, 2005;
Atkinson et al., 2003), they perform reliably worse than MA controls. The combination of
strength and weakness shows that their spatial deficit is highly selective.
In contrast to their excellent performance for canonical objects, both WS children and
MA matches were less accurate than the CA group when viewing clear image objects
shown in unusual views—whether they were presented as line drawings or full-color
objects. Previous research suggests that identifying objects in unusual views emphasizes
the use of internal features over other sources of identity information such as global
configuration, color, texture, etc. (Lawson & Humphreys, 1999). Consistent with this, we
found that blurring the colored objects eliminated the advantage of the CA group, resulting
in complete comparability of the WS children to their CA matches in this condition.
Again, this finding of strength stands in stark contrast to the WS pattern of weakness in
other kinds of spatial tasks. Indeed, given the large difference between the WS children
and their CA matches on the standardized vocabulary measure (KBIT), and, of course, on
their IQ measures (Ms of 71 vs. 123), it is quite surprising the WS children would perform
as well as CA matches in these contexts.
These results suggest the following characterization of object identification processes
in WS. First, children with WS perform close to ceiling in identifying either full color or
line drawings of objects in canonical orientations. This suggests that some of the most
basic mechanisms of object recognition are intact in children with WS.
Second, children with WS show developmental delay or arrest compared to CA
controls in their ability to identify objects in unusual orientations. In these conditions, they
are indistinguishable from younger, normally developing children of the same mental age.
This suggests that, relative to CA matches (but not MA matches), the unusual orientation
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510504
condition is disproportionately difficult for WS children. The difference between CA and
MA matches further suggests that the ability to recognize objects under unusual
orientations increases between the ages of 6 and 12 in normally developing children,
pointing to the possibility that recognition under unusual orientation engages different
mechanisms from recognition under canonical orientation.
Third, showing objects in a blurred format decreased object identification for all
participants, but of the three groups of children, it had the least impact on the WS group.
We speculate that WS children may rely more on ‘global’ or low frequency information to
identify objects, even when they are presented in clear format, so blurring has less of an
effect. A weakness in attending to internal detail in WS participants is consistent with
other findings as well. For example, Pani et al. (1999) found in a visual search task that WS
participants had more difficulty than controls in switching from a global level of
organization to a local one. Similarly, Hoffman et al. (2003) found that WS children,
unlike MA controls, continued to process to-be-ignored objects even when they were
physically segregated from a cued target object.
The overall pattern suggests both sparing and compromise in Williams syndrome
across different mechanisms of object recognition. Canonical object recognition in WS
appears to be spared in the sense that performance was close to ceiling, indistinguishable
from MA controls and, although statistically different from CA controls, very close in an
absolute sense. The qualitative similarity to the control groups further emphasizes that the
WS children are not likely to be carrying out the task in some different manner, using
different strategies to recognize the objects.
In contrast, the results for unusual viewpoints suggest a much weaker sense of sparing,
and the possibility that some of the mechanisms engaged for this kind of recognition
reflect breakdown in WS. Here, the WS children also showed strength in object
recognition, with performance far exceeding chance, and with qualitative similarity to
normal CA matches and adults. However, their performance decrement relative to
canonical views was greater than that of CA matches or adults, though it was the same as
that observed among MA matched children. This suggests that the specific mechanisms
used for recognition under unusual perspectives may be somewhat impaired relative to
chronological age, but not mental age. This contrasts strongly with the pattern for the
hallmark spatial deficit (i.e. the DAS block task) where our WS participants performed at
the level of four-year-olds, and shows that object recognition—even under the difficult
conditions of unusual viewpoint—is a distinct strength.
The general finding that unusual viewpoints are relatively difficult echoes a robust
pattern found in the object recognition literature (Palmieri & Gauthier, 2004). The
appearance of this pattern among all of our groups suggests that there is a similar
functional division between known viewpoints and highly unusual ones across the groups.
This conjecture of similarity in architecture is further supported by the detailed findings of
similarity across groups in response types and in the particular objects that people found
more or less difficult to identify. Over objects, there was considerable variation in part
structure, and in occlusion of parts under unusual viewpoints. It is not surprising,
therefore, that there were differences in how difficult or easy the objects were to accurately
identify. However, to the extent that these factors mattered, they appear to have mattered
to the same degree for all groups.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 505
How can we explain the finding of special difficulty for WS and MA matches for
unusual orientations? The relative difficulty of unusual viewpoints among WS individuals
is significant for several reasons. First, some studies have found that unusual viewpoints
tend to activate more parietal regions of the brain (Sugio et al., 1999), and people with
parietal lobe damage can have difficulty recognizing objects from these viewpoints
(Warrington & Taylor, 1973). The relative difficulty among WS children of identifying
unusual viewpoint objects is consistent with the hypothesis that WS is primarily a dorsal
stream, or a parietal lobe deficit that may also interact with frontal lobe executive functions
(Atkinson et al, 2003; Reiss et al., 2005). Although several studies of object recognition in
adults and monkey have found some sensitivity to viewpoint invariance in the IT cortex
(Booth & Rolls, 1998), the bulk of current research suggests that this part of cortex
computes viewpoints close to experienced ones (Palmieri & Gauthier, 2004). The
viewpoints that we presented were quite unusual and in some cases rather extreme (e.g.
cheeseburger viewed from directly above, a stool from directly underneath). Identifying
objects under such conditions may require visual attention to segment and search for
diagnostic object parts (Perrett et al, 1998) which would require participation by the
parietal areas of the brain, even if object recognition is in most cases carried out by the
ventral stream. If so, the similarity of the WS children to their mental age matches would
suggest that these parietal functions are not normally mature until after 6 years of age, and
that in WS, they do not mature until adolescence or later, if at all. Interestingly, the same
selective deficit in recognizing unusual views is seen in older subjects (Dror & Kosslyn,
1998) and may be due to the degradation in frontal lobe functioning that occurs with age.
The strengths in the object recognition system in children with Williams syndrome
provide another piece of the puzzle concerning the nature of their spatial deficit. Previous
findings have shown that there is strength in face recognition (Bellugi et al., 1988; Tager-
Flusberg et al., 2005), perception of biological motion and motion coherence (Jordan et al.,
2002; Reiss et al., 2004), and certain aspects of spatial language (Lakusta & Landau, 2005;
Landau & Hoffman, 2005; Landau & Zukowski, 2003). The present results suggest that
fundamental mechanisms of object recognition are also a distinct strength in WS, but that
recognizing objects from highly unusual viewpoints is either delayed or permanently
impaired. We emphasize that this delay or impairment is quantitative rather than
qualitative, as the details of error patterns were highly similar across groups.
The success seen in identifying common objects in the present studies contrasts sharply
with WS children’s performance in tasks of spatial construction (Bellugi et al., 1988;
Hoffman, Landau & Pagani 2003; Mervis et al., 1999). Impairment in these tasks appears
to be due to impairments in at least two aspects of spatial representations—mirror image
structure of individual blocks and spatial relationships between blocks (Hoffman et al.,
2003). For example, children with WS perform much more poorly than mental-age
matched children when they must match blocks that are split by color to their identical
mates in the context of blocks that are mirror images of the targets. Errors in this task
reveal that WS children have great difficulty in retaining block ‘handedness’. Importantly,
the object recognition system is relatively insensitive to such handedness (Baylis &
Driver, 2001), which is more reliably encoded by more parietal functions (Priftis, Rusconi,
Umilta & Zorzi, 2003), suspected to be part of the WS deficit. Given the importance of
being able to identify the same object across varying viewpoints, it seems plausible that
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510506
success at object recognition can co-exist with impaired representation of spatial
relationships such as mirror-image relationships.
The emerging picture of strengths and weaknesses within the spatial representational
systems has suggested to some that the WS spatial impairment is primarily a dorsal stream
deficit (Atkinson et al., 1997; Brown, et al., 2003; Wang, Doherty, Rourke & Bellugi,
1995). Recent brain imaging evidence shows that people with WS show an absence of
parietal activation during visual-construction tasks, an abnormally low level of parietal
activation while matching complex geometric stimuli (Meyer-Lindenberg et al., 2004) as
well as volume reduction in the superior parietal lobes (Eckert et al., 2005). The relative
difficulty experienced by WS children in recognizing objects under unusual viewpoints is
consistent with these findings. In addition, the strengths in object recognition found in our
experiments are consistent with the idea that functions of the ventral stream-including face
and object recognition and perception of biological motion-have the same cognitive
structure as in normal individuals.
Overall, our results suggest sparing of the object recognition system, whose specialty is
recognition of objects under canonical or neighboring—but not unusual—viewpoints.
Over both experiments, performance of WS children was remarkably strong, and crucially,
indistinguishable from normal people in its qualitative nature. The two areas of
quantitative difference we found in WS children were reduced effects of blurring and
increased effects of unusual viewpoint. We have speculated that the reduced effects of blur
likely reflect a tendency to carry out object recognition by emphasizing global spatial
structure over specific spatial features. But we emphasize that this is a matter of degree,
which does not appear to change the fundamental nature or structure of the object
recognition system.
The differences in unusual viewpoint point to a different matter. If recognition of
unusual views engages the parietal areas, and these areas are less well-activated in people
with WS, then this would explain their relative weakness in recognizing objects from
unusual views. Once again, however, we emphasize that this is a matter of degree, since
the WS children were comparable to MA matches, who are considerably younger. We
speculate that normal developmental processes might result in more powerful parietal
functions between the ages of 6 and 12, and if so, the weakness of WS children might
reflect arrest of these functions at an early functional age of around 6.
Interestingly, the idea of differential sparing and damage over the ventral and dorsal
streams in development is pleasantly consistent with two rather different ideas about the
consequences of genetic deficit. It is consistent with the idea that genetic deficits have
molecular effects on development, which could plausibly interact with timing to produce
damage to different regions of the brain. But it is also consistent with the idea that
cognitive systems with different computational and functional properties might undergo
different degrees of sparing and damage due to developmental brain damage. Thus the
findings contribute to our growing understanding of the complex cognitive consequences
of genetic variation (see, e.g. Marcus & Fisher, 2003).
Most importantly, we believe, our findings suggest a functional separation between
basic mechanisms of object recognition and other aspects of spatial representation, which
we have here observed to be the consequence of a developmental and genetic impairment.
The mechanisms by which such functional separation emerges are not known at present.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 507
However, the converging evidence suggesting both ventral and parietal mechanisms of
object recognition shows that there may be ways for a genetic deficit to have local effects
on brain development as well as more molar consequences for the development of
different cognitive systems.
Acknowledgements
This research was supported by grants #12 FY01-87 and 12 FY98-0194 from the March
of Dimes Foundation, and from BCS #9808585 and #0117744 from the National Science
Foundation. We thank the participating children and their families, and the Williams
Syndrome Association and the Mom’s Clubs of Delaware and Maryland and the Gilman
School of Baltimore, Maryland for help in recruiting participants. We also thank Gitana
Chunyo, Jay Reiss, and Andrea Zukowski for assistance in various phases of this research.
References
Aguirre, G. K., Zarahn, E., & D’Esposito, M. (1998). Neural components of topographical representation.
Proceeding of the National Academy of Sciences, 95, 839–846.
Andersen, R. A., Snyder, L. A., Bradley, D. C., & Xing, J. (1997). Multimodal representation of space in the
posterior parietal cortex and its use in planning movements. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 20, 303–330.
Atkinson, J., Braddick, O., Anker, S., Curran, W., Andrew, R., Wattam-Bell, J., et al. (2003). Neurobiological
models of visuospatial cognition in children with Williams syndrome: Measures of dorsal-stream and frontal
function. In C. B. Mervis, Developmental neuropsychology. Williams syndrome (Vol.23(1–2)), 139–172.
Special issue.
Atkinson, J., King, J., Braddick, O., Nokes, L., Anker, S., & Braddick, F. (1997). A specific deficit of dorsal
stream function in Williams’ syndrome. Neuroreport, 8, 1919–1922.
Baragwanath, B. A., & Turnbull, O. H. (2002). Central executive secondary tasks in object recognition: An
analogue of the unusual views deficit in the neurologically normal? Brain and Cognition, 48(2–3), 268–272.
Baylis, G. C., & Driver, J. (2001). Shape-coding in IT cells generalizes over contrast and mirror reversal, but not
figure-ground reversal. Nature Neuroscience, 4(9), 937–942.
Behrmann, M., & Avidan, G. (2005). Congenital prosopagnosia: face-blind from birth. Trends in cognitive
science, 9(4), 180–187.
Bellugi, U., Marks, S., Bihrle, A., & Sabo, H. (1988). Dissociation between language and cognitive functions in
Williams syndrome. In D. Bishop, & K. Mogford (Eds.), Language development in exceptional circumstances
(pp. 177–189). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Belmonte, M. K., & Yurgelun-Todd, D. A. (2003). Anatomic dissociation of selective and suppressive processes
in visual attention. Neuroimage, 19(1), 180–189.
Benton, A. L. (1967). Constructional apraxia and the minor hemisphere. Confinia Neurologica, 29, 1–16.
Biederman, I. (1987). Recognition-by-components: A theory of human image understanding. Psychological
Review, 94, 115–147.
Bihrle, A. M., Bellugi, U., Delis, D., & Marks, S. (1989). Seeing either the forest or the trees: Dissociation in
visuospatial processing. Brain and Cognition, 11, 37–49.
Booth, M. C. A., & Rolls, E. T. (1998). View-invariant representations of familiar objects by neurons in the
inferior temporal visual cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 8, 510–523.
Bridgeman, B., Gemmer, A., Forsman, T., & Huemer, V. (2000). Processing spatial information in the
sensorimotor branch of the visual system. Vision Research, 40, 3539–3552.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510508
Brown, J. H., Johnson, M. H., Paterson, S. J., Gilmore, R., Longhi, E., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2003). Spatial
representation and attention in toddlers with Williams syndrome and down syndrome. Neuropsychologia,
1553, 1–10.
Bulthoff, H. H., Edelman, S. Y., & Tarr, M. J. (1995). How are three-dimensional objects represented in the brain?
Cerebral Cortex, 5(3), 247–260.
Clahsen, H., & Almazan, M. (1998). Syntax and morphology in Williams syndrome. Cognition, 68(3), 167–198.
Colby, C. L., & Goldberg, M. E. (1999). Space and attention in parietal cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience,
22, 319–349.
Deruelle, J., Mancini, M. O., Livel, M., Casse-Perot, C., & de Schoon, S. (1999). Configural and local processing
of faces in children with Williams syndrome. Brain and Cognition, 41, 276–298.
Dilks, D., Landau, B., & Hoffman, J.E. (2005). Vision for perception and vision for action: Normal and unusual
development. Manuscript submitted.
Dror, I. E., & Kosslyn, S. M. (1998). Age degradation in top-down processing: Identifying objects from canonical
and noncanonical viewpoints. Experimental Aging Research, 24(3), 203–216.
Duchaine, B., & Nakayama, K. (2005). Dissociations in face and object recognition in developmental
prosopagnosia. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience .
Eckert, M. A., Hu, D., Eliez, S., Bellugi, U., Galaburda, A., Korenberg, J., et al. (2005). Evidence for superior
parietal impairment in Williams syndrome. Neurology, 64, 152–153.
Elliot, C. D. (1990). Differential ability scales. New York, USA: The Psychological Corporation, Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, Inc..
Ewart, A. K., Morris, C. A., Atkinson, D., Jin, W., Sternes, K., Spallone, P., et al. (1993). Hemizygosity at the
elastin locus in a developmental disorder, Williams syndrome. Nature Genetics 5, 11–16.
Farah, M. J. (2000). The cognitive neuroscience of vision. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.
Farran, E. K., Jarrold, C., & Gathercole, S. E. (2003). Divided attention, selective attention, and drawing:
Processing preferences in Williams syndrome are dependent on the task administered. Neuropsychologia, 41,
676–687.
Frangiskakis, J. M., Ewart, A. K., Morris, C. A., Mervis, C. B., Bertrand, J., Robinson, B. F., et al. (1996). LIM-
kinase1 hemizygosity implicated in impaired visuospatial constructive cognition. Cell, 86(1), 59–69.
Frith, U. (1992). Autism: Explaining the enigma. Oxford, England: Blackwell Publishers.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R., Brown, A., Carey, S., Gelman, R., & Keil, F. (1991). Lessons from animal learning for the study
of cognitive development. In S. Carey, & R. Gelman (Eds.), The epigenesis of mind: Essays on biology and
cognition (pp. 3–36). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.
Grill-Spector, K., & Kanwisher, N. (2005). Visual recognition. As soon as you know it is there, you know what it
is. Psychological Science, 16(2), 152–160.
Hermer, L., & Spelke, E. S. (1996). Modularity and development: The case of spatial reorientation. Cognition, 61,
195–232.
Hoffman, J. E., Landau, B., & Pagani, J. (2003). Spatial breakdown in spatial construction: Evidence from eye
movements in children with Williams syndrome. Cognitive Psychology, 46, 260–301.
Hughes, H. C., Nozawa, G., & Kitterle, F. (1996). Global precedence, spatial frequency channels, and the
statistics of natural images. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 8(3), 197–230.
Humphreys, G. W., & Riddoch, M. J. (1984). Routes to object constancy—implications from neurological
impairments of object constancy. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A—Human
Experimental Psychology, 36(3), 385–415.
Jordan, H., Reiss, J. E., Hoffman, J. E., & Landau, B. (2002). Intact perception of biological motion in the face of
profound spatial deficits: Williams syndrome. Psychological Science, 13(2), 162–167.
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1998). Development itself is the key to understanding developmental disorders. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 2(10), 389–398.
Karmiloff-Smith, A., Thomas, M., Annaz, D., Humphreys, K., Ewing, S., Brace, N., et al. (2004). Exploring the
Williams syndrome face-processing debate: The importance of building developmental trajectories. Journal
of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 45(7), 1258–1274.
Kaufman, A., & Kaufman, N. (1990). Kaufman brief intelligence test. Minnesota: American Guidance Service.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510 509
Kosslyn, S. M., Alpert, N. M., Thompson, W. L., Chabris, C. F., Rauch, S. L., & Anderson, A. K. (1994).
Identifying objects seen from different viewpoints—a pet investigation. Brain, 117, 1055–1071.
Kourtzi, Z., Erb, M., Grodd, W., & Bulthoff, H. (2003). Representation of the perceived 3D object shape in the
human lateral occipital complex. Cerebral Cortex, 13, 911–920.
Lakusta, L., & Landau, B. (2005). Starting at the end: The importance of goals in spatial language. Cognition .
Landau, B., & Hoffman, J. E. (2005). Parallels between spatial cognition and spatial language: Evidence from
Williams syndrome. Journal of Memory and language, 53(2), 163–185.
Landau, B., & Zukowski, A. (2003). Objects, motions, and paths: Spatial language of children with Williams
syndrome. In C. B. Mervis (Ed.), Developmental neuropsychology (Special Issue).
Lawson, R., & Humphreys, G. W. (1999). The effects of view in depth on the identification of line drawings and
silhouettes of familiar objects: Normality and pathology. Visual Cognition, 6(2), 165–195.
Livingstone, M., & Hubel, D. (1988). Segregation of form, color, movement, and depth: Anatomy, physiology,
and perception. Science, 240(4853), 740–749.
Logothetis, N. K., Pauls, J., Bulthoff, H. H., & Poggio, T. (1994). View-dependent object recognition by
monkeys. Current Biology, 4(5), 401–414.
Logothetis, N. K., & Sheinberg, D. L. (1996). Visual object recognition. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 19,
577–621.
Marcus, G., & Fisher, S. E. (2003). FOXP2 in focus: What can genes tell us about speech and language? Trends in
Cognitive Science, 7(6), 257–262.
Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman.
Mervis, C. B., Morris, C. A., Bertrand, J., & Robinson, B. F. (1999). Williams syndrome: Findings from an
integrated program of research. In H. Tager-Flusberg (Ed.), Neurodevelopmental disorders. Developmental
cognitive neuroscience (pp. 65–110). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Meyer-Lindenberg, A., Kohn, P., Mervis, C.B., Kippenhan, J.S., Olsen, R.A., & Morris, C.A., et al. (in press).
Neural basis of genetically determined visuospatial construction deficit in Williams syndrome. Neuron.
Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. New York: Oxford University Press.
Morris, C., Ewart, A. K., Sternes, K., Spallone, P., Stock, A. D., Leppert, M., et al. (1994). Williams syndrome:
Elastin gene deletions. American Journal of Human Genetics, 55(Suppl), A89.
Morrison, D. J., & Schyns, P. G. (2001). Usage of spatial scales for the categorization of faces, objects, and
scenes. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 8(3), 454–469.
Moscovitch, M., Winocur, G., & Behrmann, M. (1997). What is special about face recognition? Nineteen
experiments on a person with visual object agnosia and dyslexia but normal face recognition. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience, 9(5), 555–604.
Newcombe, N. S., & Huttenlocher, J. (2000). Making space: The development of spatial representation and
reasoning. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Newsome, W. T., & Pare, E. B. (1988). A selective impairment of motion perception following lesions of the
medial temporal visual area (MT). Journal of Neuroscience, 8, 2201–2211.
O’Hearn, K., Landau, B., & Hoffman, J. E. (2005). Multiple object tracking in people with Williams syndrome
and in normally developing children. Psychological Science .
Palmieri, T. J., & Gauthier, I. (2004). Visual object understanding. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 5, 291–304.
Pani, J. R., Mervis, C. B., & Robinson, B. F. (1999). Global spatial organization by individuals with Williams
syndrome. Psychological Science, 10(5), 453–458.
Perrett, D. I., Oram, M. W., & Ashbridge, E. (1998). Evidence accumulation in cell populations responsive
to faces: An account of generalisation of recognition without mental transformations. Cognition, 67(1–2),
111–145.
Pietrini, P., Furey, M. L., Ricciardi, E., Gobbini, M. I., Wu, W. H. C., Cohen, L., et al. (2004). Beyond sensory
images: Object-based representation in the human ventral pathway. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America, 101(15), 5658–5663.
Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New York: Harper Collins.
Priftis, K., Rusconi, E., Umilta, C., & Zorzi, M. (2003). Pure agnosia for mirror stimuli after right inferior parietal
lesion. Brain, 126, 908–919.
Reiss, J., Hoffman, J.E., & Landau, B. (2005). Motion processing specialization in Williams syndrome. Vision
Research, in press.
B. Landau et al. / Cognition 100 (2006) 483–510510
Schenk, T., & Zihl, J. (1997). Visual motion perception after brain damage: II. Deficits in form-from-motion
perception. Neuropsychologia, 35(9), 1299–1310.
Spelke, E. S., & Newport, E. L. (1998). Nativism, empiricism, and the development of knowledge. In R. M.
Lerner, & W. Damon, Theoretical models of human development.5th ed. Handbook of child psychology (Vol.
1) (pp. 275–285). New York: Wiley.
Sugio, T., Inui, T., Matsuo, K., Matsuzawa, M., Glover, G. H., & Nakai, T. (1999). The role of the posterior
parietal cortex in human object recognition: A functional magnetic resonance imaging study. Neuroscience
Letters, 276(1), 45–48.
Tager-Flusberg, H., Plesa-Skwerer, D., & Faja, S. (2003). People with Williams syndrome process faces
holistically. Cognition, 89(1), 11–24.
Tanaka, J. W., & Presnell, L. M. (1999). Color diagnosticity in object recognition. Perception and Psychophysics,
61, 1140–1153.
Tanaka, J. W., Weiskopf, D., & Williams, P. (2001). The role of color in high-level vision. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 5, 211–215.
Tanaka, K. (1996). Inferotemporal cortex and object vision. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 19, 109–139.
Tarr, M., & Pinker, S. (1990). When does human object recognition use a viewer-centered reference frame?
Psychological Science, 1, 253–256.
Turnbull, O. H., Denis, M., Mellet, E., Ghaem, O., & Carey, D. (2001). The processing of visual-spatial
information: Neuropsychological and neuroimaging investigations. In M. Denis, R. H. Logie, C. Cornoldi, M.
de Vega, & J. Engelkamp (Eds.), Imagery, language, and visuo-spatial thinking (pp. 81–108). East Sussex
Psychology Press.
Ungerleider, L. G., & Mishkin, M. (1982). Two cortical visual systems. In D. J. Ingle, M. A. Goodale, & R. J. W.
Mansfield (Eds.), Analysis of visual behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Vaina, L. M., LeMay, M., Bienfang, D. C., Choi, A. Y., & Nakayama, K. (1990). Intact ‘biological motion’ and
‘structure from motion’ perception in a patient with impaired motion mechanisms: A case study. Visual
Neuroscience, 5, 353–369.
Wang, P. P., Doherty, S., Rourke, S. B., & Bellugi, U. (1995). Unique profile of visuo-perceptual skills in a
genetic syndrome. Brain and Cognition, 29(1), 54–65.
Warrington, E. K., & Taylor, A. M. (1973). The contribution of the right parietal lobe to object recognition.
Cortex, 9, 152–164.